Logic & Programming

Danko Ilik's research blog
<– home page

A new version of this draft paper has been posted here: https://arxiv.org/abs/2401.13304

Hugo Herbelin is the principal author of this paper.

For some earlier preliminary work see my PhD thesis and the formalization. (this old formalization will be updated soon)

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

По покана на Филозофското друштво на Македонија и Институтот за филозофија при УКИМ, на 13. јануари 2024 одржав предавање на Зум со следнава содржина:

Во ова предавање ќе ги објасниме феномените на комплетност и на некомплетност на формалните логички системи, од нивната историска генеза, преку теоремите на Гедел и на Кирби-Парис, па сѐ до некои од перспективите кои овие резултати ги отвориле или ги оставиле отворени до денешен ден.

Линк до слајдовите: https://iaddg.net/danko/den-na-logikata-2024.pdf

Видеото онлајн: https://blog.iaddg.net/dash/sdl2024/

Видеото за симнување преку торент: https://iaddg.net/danko/sdl2024.torrent

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

by Kawano, Tomoaki; Matsuda, Naosuke; Takagi, Kento

The paper studies the equivalence of intuitionistic and classical validity in propositional logic for a language that contains as the only logicial connectives the ones that represent monotonic Boolean formulas.

It is shown that, for this class of formulas, intuitionistic and classical validity coincide. The notion of classical validity is the usual one (sometimes called Tarski semantics), while, for the notion of intuitionistic validity, the authors use what they call extended Kripke interpretation: the interpretation consists in, for every connective, prefixing a universal quantification $v\ge w$ (meaning ``in a possible world $v$ extending the world $w$'') before the classical interpretation of the connective.

The result is interesting, because usually intuitionistic and classical validity are shown to coincide for classes of formulas such as the so called “negative” formulas (that exclude the authentically intuitionistic connectives of disjunction and existential quantification). The class of monotone Boolean formulas thus in a way generalizes the class of negative ones.

The result shown is said to answer an open question posed by van der Giessen about the proof theory of inuitionistic and classical natural deduction calculi, however in the paper the link between the model theory developed in the paper and the proof theory of the open question is not made in sufficient detail (is there a soundness and completeness theorem for the notion of validity used with respect to the calculi?).

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

My PhD student Wendlasida Ouedraogo defended his PhD thesis on Source code optimization for safety critical software at the École Polytechnique in Palaiseau.

He showed how to do provably correct transformations of source-code for a fragment of the Ada language, used in real-world critical software, inside the Coq proof assistant. Using such transformations, one can optimize programs at the entry of a compiler, and does not pose the burden on proving simulation theorems between various compiler intermediate languages, like it is usually done (ex. in CompCert).

He also developed a tool-chain to write provably correct lexers, CoqLex, lexing previously being a compiling phase that was not done formally.

Congratulations and the best of luck to Wendlasida!

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

This book shows how to formalize some very basic mathematical notions from Logic, Abstract Algebra, Analysis, Linear Algebra, Differential Equations and Probability Theory, inside the functional programming language Haskell. Haskell is appropriate for expressing such notions since it encourages the use of high-order functions (resulting in concise, category-theory-like formulations), its variables are immutable (just like in Mathematics, eliminating computational side-effects related to variable mutation in imperative programming languages), it has algebraic data types (allowing inductive/recursive formulations and reasoning), and type classes (useful for treating mathematical theories in a compositional way). These same features are shared by proof assistant software such as Coq, which have been used extensively for formalization of Mathematics, however, what is different in the approach of this book, with respect to formalization efforts in settings with richer type systems, is that it allows one to build up an abstract mathematical concept more rapidly and experiment with it computationally, making it an interesting setting for doing experimental mathematics.

The book could be useful (indeed, it started as a coursebook for undergraduate students) for Mathematics students studying functional programming or Computer Science students studying Mathematics, but it could also be useful for researchers learning how to efficiently formalize their favorite mathematical theory inside a proof assistant. The formulations of the exponential function, the Laplace transform and the “axiomatization” of probability are elegant (concise!). One could perhaps regret the absence of definition of real numbers in the framework (real numbers are treated abstractly).

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

The paper studies the algebraic notion of Jacobson radical as a set theoretic notion. For a logician, it seems easiest to understand the Jacobson radical logically : the radical $\text{Jac}(T)$ of a theory $T$ is the set of all propositions $a$, such that an inconsistency of $a$ with a proposition $b$ translates to an inconsistency of $T$ with the proposition $b$: $$ \text{Jac}(T) = \{ a ~|~ \forall b(a,b\vdash\bot \to T,b\vdash\bot)\}. $$It is a concept used in logic, for instance, in the construction of maximally consistent extensions in the proof of the completeness theorem.

The paper studies a generalized set-theoretic formulation of the Jacobson radical and shows how it is applicable both in algebra and in logic. The generalization is obtained by replacing the algebraic statement $1\in\langle a,b\rangle$ and the logical $a,b\vdash\bot$ by a predicate $R(a,b)$ on subsets $a,b$ of the universe, called an ``inconsistency predicate''.

It is shown (Theorem 1) that the membership to the Jacobson radical is an inductively generated relation, and that this holds constructively, in CZF.

In Theorem 2, it is shown, via Theorem 1, Raoult's Open Induction principle and classical logic, that $\text{Jac}(U)$ is equal to the intersection of all possible maximally consistent extensions of $U$; this holds in ZFC.

The paper then gives application to algebra and logic, among which that the universal closure of Theorem 2 is equivalent to the axiom of choice (Proposition 3) and the derivation of Glivenko's theorem for propositional logic.

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

The paper preciselly formalizes Martin-Löf constructive type theory with the W-type (inductive definitions) and one universe, in its intensional and extensional variants, and in its variants “à la Tarski” and “à la Russell”, as well as a version/extension of classical Kripke-Platek set theory. It is then shown how to interpret the extensional type theory into Kripke-Platek set theory, from which an upper bound on the proof-theoretic strength is obtained. Together with previous results on a lower bound for intensional type theory (and an embedding into the extensional one), one obtains as a precise characterisation for the proof-theoretic strength of all variants of type theory the ordinal ψΩ1ΩI+ω.

Actually this is the most precise and succinct formulation of type theory that I have seen and should be helpful for relative interpretations of/inside type theory as well as implementing proof tools.

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

Paper by Yoshiki Nakamura and Naosuke Matsuda

Let IL and CL denote the fragments of intutionistic and classical propositional logic having implication as the sole logical connective. Call a formula (a theorem) α of CL “minimal in CL” if α cannot be obtained by substituting in another formula β ∈ CL a propositional variable p by any formula γ. In a way, α being minimal in CL means that α is apt to be an axiom (schema) of an intermediate logic, since its form is general enough that it cannot be obtained as an instantiation of another more general axiom (schema). IL and CL themselves can be completely axiomatized by such formulas and a question was posed by Komori and Kashima whether one can axiomatize a proper intermediate logic using such a formula.

The authors show that it can be done, by displaying an explicit formula G', a variant of and equivalent to the formula G := ((a → b) → c) → ((b → a) → c) → c, which when added to IL produces the intermediate Gödel-Dummett logic. One could not simple take G to be the required formula, because it is not minimal in CL.

The authors also discuss three related open problems.

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net

The paper studies the notions of continuity that arise from inductively generated neighborhood functions and from functions NN → N having a bar recursive modulus of continuity, in a strictly constructive context (constructive reverse mathematics).

The inductively generated neighborhood function (called Brouwer operations in the paper) are given by two constructors of an inductive set K, L : N → K and Sup : (N → K) → K, and an associated (primitive / structurally decreasing) recursor R satisfying the equations

Ruf (Lx) = ux Ruf (Supφ) = f φ(λx.Ruf (φx)).

A function ξ is a bar recursor for a function Y : (N → N) → N (the stopping condition for Spector’s bar recursion) if

ξGHs = Gs when Y (ˆs) < |s| ξGHs = Hs(λx.ξGH(s∗〈x〉)) when Y (ˆs) ≥ |s|.

The recursion in this case is not primitive / structurally decreasing as in the case of Brouwer operations.

While usual/general neighborhood functions can be simply be seen as continuous moduli for the functions they induce, in the strictly constructive setting, the relation between inductively generated neighborhood functions and the continuity of functions they induce is more subtle and the subject of this paper. In either classical mathematics (in presence of classical logic and dependent choice) or in intuitionistic mathematics (in presence of bar induction and strong continuity for numbers), all neighborhood functions are inductively defined. Similarly, the relation between bar induction and bar recursion has not been extensively studied in the strictly constructive setting.

A first result of the paper is that a function Y : (N → N) → N is induced by a Brouwer operation if and only if it has a bar recursive modulus of continuity (Theorem 4.15).

A second contribution of the paper is the introduction of the following equivalence-of-continuity principles.

BC: Every continuous function Y : (N → N) → N is induced by a Brouwer operation / has a bar recursive modulus.

BCc: Every continuous function Y : (N → N) → N with a continuous modulus is induced by a Brouwer operation / has a bar recursive modulus.

It is shown in Proposition 5.1 that BCc is equivalent to decidable bar induction, in the presence of the axiom of countable choice and the axiom of choice for functions N → N and quantifier-free formulas. BC is equivalent to continuous bar induction, in the presence of the axiom of countable choice and the axiom of choice for functions N → N and Π01 formulas.

A third contribution of the paper is the transposition of the previous results in the settings of Cantor space and uniform continuity.

Comment here: @danko@mamot.fr Follow using the Fediverse ID: @danko@blog.iaddg.net